Anteprima
Vedrai una selezione di 20 pagine su 98
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 1 Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 2
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 6
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 11
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 16
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 21
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 26
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 31
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 36
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 41
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 46
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 51
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 56
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 61
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 66
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 71
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 76
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 81
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 86
Anteprima di 20 pagg. su 98.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Teorie della rappresentazione - III modulo Pag. 91
1 su 98
D/illustrazione/soddisfatti o rimborsati
Disdici quando
vuoi
Acquista con carta
o PayPal
Scarica i documenti
tutte le volte che vuoi
Estratto del documento

Animism and the Movement of the Parasol

Since he had not observed so large a thing as a parasol does moved, he writes. The dog knows that a parasol cannot move autonomously. Therefore, its movement must be provoked by another living being, whose mysterious presence elicits the dog's reaction. So, for Spencer, the parasol incident was simply a momentary error and even humans can temporarily err. In this perspective:

So, if for Darwin animism is an instantaneous lapse into the animal, for Spencer it depends on a momentaneous suspension of rational faculties. 58 Darwin's animal example becomes further embellished in the interpretation offered by Tito Vignoli, the animal psychologist author of the book Myth and Science.

The movement of pain, produced by an object to which habit had rendered him indifferent That Vignoli interprets as the first stage of myth deeply embedded in the organic memory of the living being. In fact, if we follow the interpretation of Spyros Papapetros in his study On the Animation of the Inorganic (2012), we

One could argue that:

Besides, we can also notice that the example at issue here, revolving around the movement of a parasol hit by the breeze, reminds us of the etymological route of animation, in Latin, anima, or soul, based on the Greek animòs, meaning precisely the wind, the breeze or simply air, indicating the breath that animates the living beings. It is the animals that tend to attribute life in connection with the presence of movement, but one thing is to attribute life to a moving thing, while to grant animation to inert entities is a totally different thing.

In this sense, Tylor draws a distinction between animism and fetishism. Unlike fetishism, animism does not refer to a singular object, instead:

And the soul traverses both the physical and the metaphysical world. However, within the animist conception, the anima is a mobile energy that is independent from the bodies it infuses. Ethnographers like Wund, Durkheim and Moss describe the belief in such a mobile force as the

Intrinsic principle of the pre-animistic stage or animatism, also mentioned by Freud in Totem and Taboo (1913). Animatism describes the animation of all objects by a universal force. It is a diffuse state of force, equally spread into all objects and, therefore, it precedes the individual souls. Indeed, animistic thought can be identified in the practices of everyday life, and we could invoke a number of familiar incidents involving, as Taylor suggests, fully grown Europeans who, in the face of an accident, regress into infantile behaviour. For example, after bumping their head into furniture or a wall, otherwise sensible adults would instinctively blame the object, curse it and even hit it back. Pain is often the primary catalyst for the vivification of objects and the reflexive regression into animist mentality.

However, as Papapetros remarks:

"But, if we, that are educated in and acquainted with the values of the Western culture, are not to accept animistic beliefs as such, we still can"

practise a methodological animism. The expression comes from the Indian American anthropologist Arjun Appadurai and we will come back to that later. Methodological animism represents an effort to follow the things themselves, in that they can indicate to us a new theoretical paradigm and thereby help us reanimate the Western tradition of thought.60 This is the claim of the British anthropologist Tim Ingold. As he argues, when we speak of animism, we interpret animism from the point of view of a non-animist mentality. In animic ontology, beings do not propel themselves across a ready-made world, but rather issue forth through a world in formation. For animist cultures, there is not an already accomplished soul that comes to infuse otherwise inanimate things, but rather a soul always in formation, always changing and developing. To its inhabitants, this weather world, embracing both sky and earth, is a source of astonishment, but not surprise. So, reanimating the Western tradition of thought means,

For Ingold, recover the sense of astonishment, vanished from official science. There are a bunch of sciences of the Western propensity to an animist conception, for example, from time to time, the media of the Western world register a surge of excitement about the imminent prospect of discovering life on the planet Mars. This is indeed a fascinating perspective, but what it is exactly that scientists hope or expect to find on the surface on the planet? And, if there were life on a planet other than the Earth, how would we recognise it when we see it? In fact, what we know from ethnography is that people do not always agree about what is a life and what is not and that, even when they do agree, it might be for entirely different reasons. Animism is commonly defined as a system of beliefs that imputes life or spirit to things that are truly inert, but this convention is misleading because, first of all:

It is the dynamic transformative potential of the entire field of relation within which:

is to say that the animacy of the lifeworld is not the result of an infusion of spirit into substance, or agency into materiality, but it is ontologically prior to their differentiation. In other words, animism can be understood only in the perspective of relational ontology. Psychologists have suggested an evolutionary explanation of animistic beliefs. According to such explanations, animistic beliefs are founded upon the bedrock of an unconscious predisposition that even educated adults share with children and supposively primitive folks, a predisposition to act as though animated objects are actually alive. In an evolutionary perspective, the argument goes that if you don't know whether something is alive or not, it is better bet to assume that it is and reckon with the consequences, since the cost of getting it wrong in some instances are always outweighed by the benefits of getting it right in others. With regards to these explanations in the domain of evolutionary psychologies,Ingold argues that this kind of explanations are shaped by what he calls the logic of inversion, a logic that is deeply sedimented within the canons of Western thought. Through inversion, the field of involvement in the world of a thing or a person, that is their behaviour and external manifestations, are converted into an interior schema of which its manifest appearance on behaviour are but at word expressions, simple externalizations. So, the organism, moving and growing along lines that bind it to the web of life, is understood as the outward expression of an inner design. This is for instance the main logic that informs the rhetoric of research in genetics, according to which the organism is identified as the genotype, that is the inner design which is held to underwrite the manifest form of the phenotype. Ingold claims that in order to understand animism beyond classic conceptions, we need to reverse this logic of inversion, in order to recover that original openness to the world, in which.Le persone che noi, cioè gli etnologi occidentali addestrati, chiamiamo animisti trovano il significato della vita. Ora, al fine di sviluppare ulteriormente lo scopo di Ingold, dobbiamo comprendere la costituzione relazionale dell'essere. Ma cos'è l'ontologia relazionale? Come possiamo ridefinire la nostra comprensione dell'animismo attraverso una costituzione relazionale dell'essere? Come sostiene Ingold, potremmo rappresentare l'organismo come un semplice cerchio, in cui l'organismo è piegato su se stesso. Con questa semplice rappresentazione, ho piegato l'organismo su se stesso, in modo che sia delineato e contenuto entro un perimetro di confini, separato da un mondo circostante, l'ambiente, con cui è destinato a interagire secondo la sua natura. Quindi, la logica dell'inversione è ciò che ci porta a pensare all'organismo come un oggetto autonomo. Ma cosa succederebbe se rappresentassimo l'organismo come una linea? In questa rappresentazione, non c'è né dentro né fuori, e nessun confine che separa i due domini. C'è un percorso lungo il quale la vita viene vissuta, una volta che si tende.

In a tissue of trails that together make up the texture of the lifeworld. The texture helps us to figure how organisms can be understood as being constituted within a relational field, not a field of interconnected points but of interwoven lines, not a network, but a meshwork.

The philosophers Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari famously linked this web to a rhizome, but Ingold prefers to refer to the image of the fungal mycelium, or we could take on the image we analyzed speaking of Bredekamp's account of images of science, the image of the coral, developed by Darwin. In this conception, what we have been accustomed to calling the environment might then be better conceived as a domain of entanglement, that is an intertwining between organisms and the matter that surrounds them.

Relational ontology is a tangle of interlaced trails, continually ravelling here and ravelling there. We must cease regarding the world as an inert substratum over which living things propel themselves about.

Like counters on a board or actors on a stage, where artifacts and the landscape take the place respectively of properties and scenery.

So, the first step to undo the Western conception of animism, would be to stop to think of life as an inner principle and think of it as a "continuous birth". Life, in the animic ontology is not an emanation but a generation of being, in a world that is not preordained but incipient, forever on the verge of the actual.

In his essay Eye and Mind, the philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty attributed precisely the same kind of sensibility, the same openness to a world in formation, to the painter. The painter's relation to the world, Merleau-Ponty writes, is not a simple physical optical one. He does not gaze upon a world that is finite and complete, and proceeds to fashion every presentation of it, in its depiction of the world. Rather, the relationship between the painter and the visible is one of continued birth, as though at every moment.

thepainter opened his eyes to the world for the first time. The vision of the painter is not of things in aworld, but of things becoming things and of the world becoming a world. The painter Paul Klee mademuch the same point in his Creative Credo (1920), when he declared that art does not reproduce the visiblebut makes visible. In their painting, painters aim to recover, behind a mundane ordinariness of the abilityto see things, the sheer astonishment of that experience of being able to see. That is what Merleau-Pontycalls the magic or the delirium of vision, and it is precisely such attitude of astonishment that Ingold wantsto bring into light.

This is the other side of the coin to the very openness to the world that is fundamental to the animic wayof being. not as a simple background or astage for events to comeNow, when Western mentality, unfamiliar with this way of being, looks at this openness, it reads it as aprimitive belief and practice. In fact, Wester’s attitude is

rather that of grasping things and phenomena within a greed of concepts and categories. That is, instead of trying to fit everything into preconceived notions and labels, we should approach the world with an open mind and a willingness to explore and understand things as they are. This requires letting go of our attachment to fixed ideas and being willing to embrace the complexity and nuance of reality. By doing so, we can gain a deeper and more authentic understanding of the world around us.
Dettagli
Publisher
A.A. 2020-2021
98 pagine
SSD Scienze storiche, filosofiche, pedagogiche e psicologiche M-FIL/04 Estetica

I contenuti di questa pagina costituiscono rielaborazioni personali del Publisher rossanaglm di informazioni apprese con la frequenza delle lezioni di Teorie della rappresentazione e dell'immagine e studio autonomo di eventuali libri di riferimento in preparazione dell'esame finale o della tesi. Non devono intendersi come materiale ufficiale dell'università Università degli Studi di Milano o del prof Dalmasso Anna Caterina.