Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
Scarica il documento per vederlo tutto.
vuoi
o PayPal
tutte le volte che vuoi
3.7. PRAGMATIC IMPLICATIONS: FACTS THAT ARE 'ACTUALIZED' AND 'STILL TO BE ACTUALIZED'
3.7.1. Presuppositions
Presupposition is a type of mental process by which a listener can reach a logical conclusion by using
additional knowledge to make sense of what is not explicit in an utterance. A presupposition is a logical
conclusion that speakers judge to be (a) true or false and (b) appropriate or non-appropriate in
reference to the context in which they say it. Presuppositions can be ascribed to a linguistic domain
between Semantics and Pragmatics, insofar as they are both:
• Co-text sensitive: semantically dependent on the textual context in which they occur;
• Context sensitive: pragmatically dependent on the actual context of the utterance.
Presuppositions are preserved in negative sentences.
e.g: Jane saw/didn't see the castle on the hill (there exists a castle on the hill)
The verbs of perception are typical instances of presuppositions triggers, which means that they are
words capable of activating certain presuppositions in the listeners' minds. Thus, for instance:
1. Try/attempt and remember/forget may be classified as Implicative Verbs when they trigger
(innescano) presuppositions implying pre-existing states.
e.g: Jim tried/did not try to open the door (the door was closed; Jim intended/ did not intend
to open it)
2. Try/attempt and remember/forget may be classified as Factive Verbs when they trigger
presuppositions concerning already actualized facts.
e.g: Jim tried/did not try opening the door (the door was closed; Jim opened/did not open the
door)
3. Stop/finish may be classified as Change of State Verbs in that they signal the passing from a
pre-existing state to a new one.
e.g: John stopped smoking (John had been smoking-ending a pre-existing state)
e.g: John stopped to smoke (John stopped [what he was doing at the moment] in order to
smoke-passing a new state)
According to Gazdar a presupposition, to be pragmatically appropriate, needs to be mutually known
by the participants in a communicative exchange interacting within shared cultural contexts.
e.g: The speaker stopped working.
CAP. IV- MODULE 11
4.5. SOCIAL/PSYCHOLOGICAL PROXIMITY AND DISTANCE: MODAL AUXILIARIES SHOULD AND
WOULD AS TONE/STYLE MARKERS
The notion of Conditional in English doesn't regard it as a Mood. The English language, in fact,
conceptualizes the notion of Conditional as part of the Indicative Mood and as a modalization of the
Present Tense in both its Simple and Perfect Aspects by means of the two modal auxiliaries would and
should. Although would and should represent the corresponding Past-Tense versions of the Present-
Tense forms of will and shall, they are not regarded as such in the context of the English
conceptualization of Conditional. The semantic notion of Conditional, in fact implies the setting of
conditions in the present time for the realization of a process in the future time.
• The Ideational Function is concerned with the way in which language enables speakers to
represent their mental image of reality;
• The Interpersonal Function is concerned with the way in which language enables speakers to
interact with other people.
The use of the Past Tense of the modal auxiliary verbs in the so-called conditional clauses needs to be
understood in its figurative sense of psychological and social distance of the Speaker from his/her
Listener. In Halliday's view, a Speaker can conceive a psychological distance from (or a psychological
proximity to) his/her Listener by activating in his/her mind the Ideational Function of language. On
the other hand, the Speaker can conceive a social distance from (or a social proximity to) his/her
Listener by means of the Interpersonal Function.
(1) Will you wait for me?
(2) Would you wait for me?
The only difference between these two sentences is pragmatic, insofar as:
• Sentence (1) indicates that the Speaker considers him/herself to be psychological and socially
closer to the Listener, and this is signalled by the modal auxiliary will that marks an informal
style and a direct tone.
• Sentence (2), the use of would marks a more formal style and a tentative tone, indicating that
the Speaker is psychologically and socially more distant from the Listener.
Halliday's notions of Tone and Style are connected to his view of Register, that is, language used
within specific situational contexts and often related to specialized fields of discourse. Tone and Style
are two aspects of Tenor that is: the Register parameter that signals the relationship of the Sender of
messages (speakers/writers) with his/her supposed Receiver, and the way in which this relationship is
reflected in the form given to the messages.
A tentative tone signals a formal style indicating the social (interpersonal) and psychological
▪ (ideational) distance between Speaker and Listener.
A direct tone, on the other hand, signals an informal style indicating the social and
▪ psychological proximity between Speaker and Listener.
4.6. MODALIZED CONDITIONAL PROCESSES
4.6.1. Present (Simple) Conditional with Modal Auxiliaries: Syntax and Semantics
The Present Simple Conditional is formed by the modal auxiliaries would/should+ the Infinitive of the
main verb. Its structures are parallel to the structures are parallel to the structures of the Future
Simple, except for the use of would and should instead of will and shall:
Affirmative
I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they/ would/should work
Negative
I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they/ wouldn't/shouldn't work
Interrogative
Would/Should I/you/he/she/it/you/they work?
Negative Interrogative
Would/Should I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they not work?
Image schema of the I-Node in a Present Simple Conditional sentence.
Semantically, the Present Simple Conditional conveys:
a. The sense of an improbable or uncertain process in the future.
e.g: I would come to see you if you were free next Monday (which is improbable or
uncertain)
b. The same sense conveyed by the Future Simple but set in a past period of time (the so called
Future in the Past).
e.g: I hope that I will/shall pass the exam. (referred to the present moment of speaking)
I hope that I would/should pass the exam (referred to a past moment in time)
4.6.2. Perfect Conditional with Modal Auxiliaries: Syntax and Semantics
For the Perfect Conditional, the focus of the conventional label is on Aspect (Perfect) only, since this
conditional form is indefinite as for its reference to Tense. In fact, it may imply either a present or a
past reflection on a failed condition in the past, depending on the context within which this
conditional form occurs.
Syntactically, the Perfect Conditional is formed with would/should + the Perfect Infinitive of the main
verb.
Affirmative
I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they would/should have worked.
Negative
I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they wouldn't/shouldn't have worked
Interrogative
Would/Should I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they have worked?
Negative Interrogative
Would/should I/you/he/she/it/we/you/they not have worked?
Semantically, the Perfect Conditional conveys:
a. The sense of an impossible process in the past time, when a condition which was expected
to occur in the future did not occur because the process necessary to realize such a condition
did not happen.
e.g: I would have come to see you if you had been free the following Monday (but
actually you were busy and I did not come).
b. The sense of the realization of a process which was considered to be impossible, due to the
fact that, in a past time, a condition which was not expected to occur in the future did actually
occur and caused the realization of such a process.
e.g: Jim shouldn't have finished his work if Fiona hadn't helped him for the whole
week.
c. The sense of an equivalent of the process expressed in the Future Perfect but set in the past
time (Future in the Past).
e.g: I hope that I will/shall have passed the exam before Christmas (referred to the
present moment of speaking- the Speaker does not know yet if he is going
to succeed or not).
I hope that I would/should have passed the exam before Christmas (referred to a
past moment in time- the Speaker now knows that he did not succeed).
4.7. PRAGMATIC DIMENSIONS OF CONDITIONAL FORMS
4.7.1. Should and Would in Discourse
The modal auxiliaries would and should keep the same semantic implications of will and shall, that
is: volition and intention for will and would, and determination and obligation for shall and should.
Should and would mark instead a more detached tone which makes the style of discourse more formal
and conventional. Such 'detached discourse more formality can be interpreted as an expression of
the Speaker's tentative proposal for a future action, or also as the Speaker's insufficient commitment
in the action that s/he is predicting for the future.
These pragmatic uses of would and should are particularly evident in political discourse. In the Tenor
of political speeches, indeed, the use of the modal auxiliaries should and would to refer to future
processes are often deliberately employed to avoid a too direct first-person involvement and
ideological commitment of the Speaker is saying is not unquestionably acceptable by Listeners. The
Speaker may prefer to use this tentative way of exploring Listeners' reactions advancing them openly.
CAP. VII- MODULE 17
COHERENCE AND INFERENCE IN CONDITIONAL SENTENCES
7.1. SEMANTIC COHERENCE AND SCHEMATIC INFERENCE IN DISCOURSE
7.1.1. Textual/Contextual Coherence
Coherence in the process of making sense of a text it is necessary to realize that in interpreting a
written text as discourse, a reader does not exclusively rely on its syntactic and lexical structure. S/he
also needs to possess the relevant knowledge to contextualize the text in the socio-cultural situation
in which it was produced. Contextualization enable the reader to provide the logical connection to
concepts and ideas expressed in the text. This process of making logical sense of the lexical and
syntactic structure of the text by means of a shared socio-cultural knowledge of situational contexts
is what we mean by Coherence.
De Beaugrande and Dressler explore the cognitive mechanism by which a reader achieves coherence
from a text to make it function as discourse in context. Coherence as one of the seven standards of
textuality representing the constitutive principles which determine the communicative quality of a
text. The other "standards of textuality" are: Cohesion, Intentionality, Acceptability, Informativity,
Situationality, Intertextuality. Moreover, to be communicatively successful within a specific socio-
cultural context, a text needs to meet three additional regulative principles which are: Efficiency,
Effectiveness and Appropriateness.
Coherence is strictly connected with the notion of Textual World which stands for the cognitive
representation of the semantic sense of a text that a reader constructs in his/her